What is Belief?

 

 

What is Belief?

 

 

For all the work that has been done on the topic of belief, do we really know what belief is?[1] What kind of state (if state it be) is the belief state? Two suggestions have been prominent: belief is a feeling and belief is a disposition. Either belief is a state of consciousness analogous to sensation (pain, seeing red, feeling sad) or it is a tendency to behave in a certain way (assenting to a proposition, combining with desire to produce action). The OED defines “believe” as “feel sure that (something) is true”, thus categorizing belief as a type of feeling: not “be sure” but “feelsure”. What that feeling might be is left undetermined, though the definition has the ring of truth. And indeed belief is connected to feeling: your feelings tend to change when you acquire a belief, and there is such a thing as feeling sure. But what about beliefs you hold without thinking about them– are those beliefs all associated with feelings? Do you feel sure that London is in England, for example, even when the thought has not crossed your mind in months? Here is where the dispositional theory suggests itself: belief isn’t an episodic state of consciousness but a readiness to act in a certain way—to respond “yes” when asked whether London is in England, say. Ramsey said belief is a “map by which we steer”, emphasizing that beliefs guide action (but do we inspect our beliefs as we inspect maps?). And certainly beliefs and dispositions are tightly connected (as are desires and dispositions): your dispositions change when you acquire a belief, and belief encourages assent behavior. But is this what a belief is? Isn’t it rather the mental state that gives rise to the disposition? What if you had a tendency to assent verbally to propositions not because you believe them but because you have been rigged up that way by a clever scientist intent on simulating the state of belief? In general, dispositional theories confound properties (states, facts) with their causal consequences; and we want to know what belief is not what it does. The OED also has this under “believe”: “accept the statement (of someone) as true”. But don’t we accept statements because of what we believe? It isn’t that the belief is the acceptance. It is hard to avoid the impression that the dictionary (and the usual philosophical theories) conflates the symptoms of belief—feelings and dispositions–with belief itself. But then what is belief itself exactly?

Are we acquainted with belief itself? We are acquainted with sensations and behavior, both signs of belief, but are we acquainted with beliefs? The answer is not obvious. If we are, it seems curious that we draw a blank when considering the nature of belief; but if we are not, why do we bandy the concept around with such confidence? Is it perhaps that the concept is logically primitive and hence admits of no explanation in other terms? But that can’t be the reason for our ignorance, because the same is true of many concepts and yet we are not blind to the nature of their reference (pain, seeing red, maybe moral goodness). Or is it that the felt ignorance is an illusion born of a mistaken assumption, namely that we only know what a mental phenomenon is if we can reduce it either to a feeling or to a disposition? Maybe we know exactly what belief is but we think we don’t because beliefs are not sensational or behavioral, these being our preferred touchstones of mental reality when thinking philosophically. But that approach, though not unsound in principle, is hard to square with an evident fact: we really don’t know what it is to believe something—we have no conception of what fact is at issue. Once belief is distinguished from its symptoms its elusiveness becomes evident (compare Hume on causation).

This leaves us with another possibility—that “believes” is really a name for an I-know-not-what that we introduce to denote something that we reasonably believe to exist but can’t properly conceptualize. Belief is thus that state, whatever it is, that has such and such symptoms and plays such and such a role but whose nature we find elusive. In short, “belief” is a theoretical term—not just in application to others but also in application to oneself. Our knowledge of belief operates at one remove from the thing itself, which is why we have such an indeterminate conception of it. A similar approach might be suggested for the concepts of meaning and the self: these too are not directly encountered constituents of consciousness, which is why we can’t reconstruct them in such terms, but they are real nonetheless, just at some epistemic distance from our cognitive faculties. That is, not all parts of what we think of as the mind exist at the same epistemic level (and not because of a detached Freudian unconscious); some are not objects of direct inspection (perceptual or introspective). The ontology of folk psychology is an amalgam of these two types of fact (and we can add desire to belief): the mind consists of directly known constituents and relatively unknown constituents. Differently stated, belief (desire, meaning, the self) is a state that we refer to but are not acquainted with; we know many of its properties, but not its intrinsic nature. We know it is a propositional attitude (but what is an attitude exactly?) and that it involves the exercise of concepts, as well as being a truth-bearer, subject to referential opacity, and capable of combining with desire to lead to action: but we don’t grasp what kind of state it is—not in its intrinsic nature. The state gives rise to inner feelings and to outer behavior, but we have no clear idea of what it is in itself. We experience shadows of it, fleeting intimations and glimpses, but we have no firm conception of the thing itself: it is just “that which gives rise to these symptoms”. Ask yourself what kind of mental state you are in when you are asleep: you have various beliefs, but what is their mode of existence exactly? You might be tempted to reach for the concept of a disposition, but we have been down that road before—what is the ground of such a disposition? Let’s face it: you don’t know what to say, and yet you don’t doubt that you are in some sort of mental state. You might sputter that you are in a “cognitive state”, but that raises the same question over again: what kind of state is that? Not a feeling state and not a disposition, but a sui generis state that confounds comprehension. As we might say, we have only a partial grasp of what belief is. And the part we don’t grasp intrigues us the most, i.e. the very being of belief.

I grant that this position might sound counterintuitive. Doesn’t the Cogito express certain knowledge (“I believe, therefore I am”)? But how can that be if we don’t know what thinking (believing) is? However, this is really not such a paradoxical position to be in: we know that we think and believe, and that this entails our existence, but it doesn’t follow that we know what thinking and believing are—or what the self is for that matter. And did Descartes ever claim anything to the contrary—did he suppose that the nature of thinking is totally transparent to us? Knowing that something exists is not the same as knowing its nature. If Descartes had claimed that thinking is processing sentences in the language of thought, he could have been wrong about that; but this wouldn’t undermine the Cogito. In fact, I would say that if you focus really hard on what is going on when you believe something you will see that nothing determinate comes into view—you never catch your belief in flagrante, as it were. And you have no clear conception of what it is that you attribute when you ascribe beliefs to others (beyond their conceptual content). Nor does knowledge of the brain help: identifying belief with neural excitation in the B-fibers, say, affords no knowledge of what belief is in the ordinary sense. The problem is that neither does anything else—crucially, not introspection. We didn’t come by the concept of belief by noticing feelings of belief in ourselves (where would those feelings to be located?), or by observing the operation of dispositions to behavior; rather, we introduced a term for a type of psychological state whose nature was not evident to us but which we were sure existed. I have evidence for my beliefs drawn from my experience (e.g. feelings of conviction), but I don’t believe in beliefs because I can grasp them whole. I see them through a glass darkly. I have a nebulous sense that certain propositions attract my assent, as if gravitationally, but what exactly my mind is up to I cannot tell. Even the strongest of our beliefs, say religious or moral or scientific beliefs, fail to disclose their inner nature—we just find ourselves filled with passionate conviction about certain things. It isn’t like feeling a headache or a hunger pang in the stomach. Nor is it like hearing a sentence in your head. It isn’t like anything.

Psychology used to be conceived as an introspective science, and then later as a science of observable behavior, but these ideas were predicated on a certain conception of the essence of the mind. Either the mind consists of inner episodes of consciousness of which we have immediate introspective awareness, or it consists of outer behavior that can be perceived externally. But the case of belief (also desire) shows that these alternatives are not exhaustive and are fundamentally on the wrong track. In so far as psychology is about belief and kindred states, it is not about feelings or behavioral dispositions, but about facts we find systematically elusive, which fit into neither category. Beliefs are not feelings and they are not dispositions to behavior, yet there are fully mental phenomena, paradigmatically so. As Hume would say, we have no impression of belief, yet belief is real and knowable (in some of its aspects).  Belief is yet another example of the limits of human cognition. Psychology thus has an elusive subject matter.[2]

 

C

[1] The background to this essay is scattered. The issues discussed bubble under the surface of Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations and are explicitly posed in Kripke’s Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language (as well as my Wittgenstein on Meaning). In addition, the emphasis on ignorance reflects my standing interest in human mysteries as they pertain to philosophy. Hume is hovering paternally in the wings. Russell makes a brief appearance.

[2] It might be said that belief is a computational state and that this gives its essential nature. There is a lot to be said about this suggestion; suffice it to remark that this doesn’t give us a conception of belief comparable to our intuitive notions of pain or seeing red. Belief may well have computational properties, but it is another thing to claim that this is what belief is (would it follow that computers believe?).

Share
24 replies
  1. jgkess@cfl.rr.com
    jgkess@cfl.rr.com says:

    The question is: are there really “natural kinds” of psychological state? Each and every alleged kind of propositional attitude seems to me a mixed bag—no functional, computational, or motivational “essence”. With respect to “belief” in particular, feelings of certainty or doubt vary with respect to scope or depth of back-ground information (not necessarily back-ground ” beliefs”). Temperament too has its sway. The question and nature of “epistemic feelings” I suppose is your larger target. In any case, I leave you with this—after having taken my migraine medicine—“Beliefs” are but the chimera of the ignorant. I’ve been reading Confucius lately.

    Reply
    • Colin McGinn
      Colin McGinn says:

      It is certainly generally assumed that there are such natural kinds–memories, perceptions, thoughts, desires, emotions, etc. Of course natural kinds can have many dimensions. Surely we don’t want to say that all this is “social construction” or sheer myth.

      Reply
  2. jgkess@cfl.rr.com
    jgkess@cfl.rr.com says:

    “Memories, perception,.thoughts, desires, emotions, etc.” .” ‘Tis all entangled”—as Johnson said of the philosophy of a worthy contemporary. The alleged discrete boundaries between folk-psychological categories are an artifact, well, of folk-psychological thinking. Dynamical-systems theory, with respect to brain function, is, I suspect, the new way to go. If you start drinking again you might find the idea more congenial!

    Reply
  3. jgkess@cfl.rr.com
    jgkess@cfl.rr.com says:

    First, no snark intended in that last Comment. Second, with respect to Joseph K.’s question: check out Jerry Fodor'[s review of a collection of Davidson’s essays. “Mouse Thoughts”. London Review of Books—2002

    Reply
  4. jgkess@cfl.rr.com
    jgkess@cfl.rr.com says:

    Jonathan Miller once described consciousness as “a kind of oil-slick” over the brain. Holism is the cognitive oil-slick over modularity. Language provides the opportunity for “considered” reflection upon one’s own instinctive or reflexive “thoughts”. Great match between Tsisipas and Thiem—or at least I hope so..

    Reply
  5. Giulio Katis
    Giulio Katis says:

    Does an individual possess a belief or does the belief possess the individual? Aspects of both appear to be in play, though neither in isolation seems right. When an adventurer, to the horror or amusement of his fellow townspeople or villagers, is about to set sail on the belief the world is not flat and there are unknown lands to discover over the horizon, psychologically what is really going on? Courage and intuition in the face of everyday accepted commonsense is at work, but it seems there is something more. A life-altering choice is being made. The concept of a bridge comes to mind for some reason, though I am not sure why. A characteristic of the mind is that it can be both open and critical. The capacity for believing (in a non-trivial way) seems to require both.

    You are right – there are things we can’t pin down with concepts, though they may have multiple manifestations that each can be.

    Reply
  6. jgkess@cfl.rr.com
    jgkess@cfl.rr.com says:

    Few are able to follow me on the matter of oil slicks and holism–awesome and compelling as the arguments for it are, this wondrous new branch of philosophical insight. It’s deserving of a cult, after the manner of “externalism”. Be sure to watch for my new book on the subject, tentatively titled, “On the Slipperiness of Belief”.

    Reply
  7. Giulio Katis
    Giulio Katis says:

    I have been thinking about your question as to whether computers could believe. Similarly, we might ask could they surrender, could they give? The answer is sort-of yes, but only in a way that doesn’t fully capture the inherent contradiction that is bridged in these acts. So to share where I’ve ended up: it’s basically to ask again what are computers. (This is as someone who spent his post-doctoral years and research fellowships with theoretical computer scientists after a PhD in pure mathematics.) Basically, computers are things we can understand without contradictions. (These probably aren’t real things at all, but just formal aspects of things. We can engineer some real things so their behaviour doesn’t much deviate from what are our expectations given our formal designs.)

    Reply
    • Colin McGinn
      Colin McGinn says:

      What people call “computers” hover between concrete machines and mathematical objects. It is doubtful that the machines really compute in a way that is independent of human interpretation (human computers do compute).

      Reply
  8. Oliver S.
    Oliver S. says:

    In addition to experientialism and dispositionalism about belief, there’s a third prominent suggestion (which is the dominant one in cognitive science, isn’t it?): representationalism. For example, Peter Carruthers thinks that “propositional attitudes are discrete structured representational states composed out of component concepts. Beliefs, for example, are not just complex dispositions of a certain sort. Rather, they are structured categorical states that give rise to various dispositions in the presence of other such states together with the normal operations of the mind.”
    (Carruthers, Peter. “On Knowing Your Own Beliefs: A Representationalist Account.” In /New Essays on Belief: Constitution, Content, and Structure/, edited by Nikolaj Nottelmann, 145-165. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2013. p. 148)

    However, if beliefs (or any other propositional attitudes) are (nonconscious) mental representations, they must be neurally realized somehow. But does the brain really contain and process (nonconscious) proposition-like *semantic* information?

    Reply
    • Colin McGinn
      Colin McGinn says:

      This type of view is not an alternative to the other two because we still need to ask about the nature of the belief relation to an internal representation. It is generally thought of as a disposition to employ internal representations in a certain way (see Field on “belief*”). Carruthers is confused, running together conceptual content and the belief relation.

      Reply
  9. Oliver S.
    Oliver S. says:

    A mental/neural representation of a proposition or state of affairs is not sufficient for a belief, because the same representation can be part of different propositional attitudes. The mere representation is attitude-neutral, so there must be some differentia specifica in virtue of which beliefs are different from other propositional attitudes: belief = representation + x. Arguably, x is a dispositional or functional factor (in relation to the representation).

    “On this view, a subject believes that P just in case she has a representation of P that plays the right kind of role—a ‘belief-like’ role—in her cognition. That is, the representation must not merely be instantiated somewhere in the mind or brain, but it must be deployed, or apt to be deployed, in ways we regard as characteristic of belief.”
    Eric Schwitzgebel: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/belief/

    Reply
  10. Dermot O’Keeffe
    Dermot O’Keeffe says:

    Yes, it’s all highly perplexing.
    I find it strange that people have been and are judged for their beliefs when, presumably, we have no direct control over them.
    We have our own noetic structures, and within them, our own normativity; this ‘delivers’ belief, and has its own dynamic. Beliefs possess us more than we possess them, I think.
    People have ( say in a Greene novel ) prayed for faith. Yes, this pays tribute to the passivity of belief, and the fact that we can wish for different beliefs and attitudes, but cannot simply affirm or choose them.
    Related to this, I think, is the issue of reason.
    If reasoning shapes my belief, then I am not responsible for it. It is delivered ineluctably. ( Maths is obvious here.)
    But if reason doesn’t shape my belief ( let’s say I am able to select beliefs aesthetically, or due to wishful thinking ) I am not responsible for them either, in a sense, as such a non-rational being would just not be considered responsible, but mentally unwell. ( I can think of certain political figures here. )
    WK Clifford was perhaps a bit too narrow on the ethics of belief. Maybe Dawkins is too!
    But they represent interesting counterweights to the view that you can believe whatever you like without rationally ‘paying for it’, so to speak.
    Given the prevalence of conspiracy theories, I suspect that the ethics of belief debate should be at the forefront of cultural issues.
    But if belief is sufficiently privatised and democratised, or seen as analogous to taste, it is perceived as private and sacrosanct, perhaps.
    Which I find troubling.

    Reply
      • Dermot O’Keeffe
        Dermot O’Keeffe says:

        I think it’s also interesting that I don’t ever confuse a memory with a day dream, or a belief with a viewpoint I am merely entertaining.
        Maybe this suggests that such mental states are ‘tagged’, but in a fashion inaccessible to conscious inspection.
        Perhaps they are tagged neurophysiologically, such that although phenomenologically similar, we can recognise them as different types of propositional attitude.

        Reply
        • Colin McGinn
          Colin McGinn says:

          I also don’t confuse a visual impression with an auditory one or a pain with a tickle. Is this because the phenomenology is so evident or because the brain has already classified it? If beliefs are “tagged” as beliefs, it would be suprising if nothing else were.

          Reply
          • Dermot O’Keeffe
            Dermot O’Keeffe says:

            I agree.
            It’s interesting that the content of a belief and a memory (say) may be identical but the attitude taken so unmistakable. And also interesting that we cannot articulate why we can discriminate between the two so readily. We just can, it seems!
            Maybe there is a largely unconscious sorting mechanism that selects, almost in a Darwinian way, claims deemed likely to be true or useful and promotes them above those views merely considered but rejected. Then tags them.
            My own belief system seems a bit Quinean, with central ones remaining rather static, and peripheral ones changing frequently and at no great cost.
            I cannot be alone, I think, in getting an almost physical pleasure from changing a long held belief. It requires then moving other furniture, accordingly, of course!
            But I should say the belief itself changes and I just read it off, so to speak.
            I never actively change a belief, and doubt if others do.
            Nietzsche refers to this somewhere in Beyond Good and Evil, I think.

Leave a Reply

Want to join the discussion?
Feel free to contribute!

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.